Based on a publication in the Millennium Film Journal, fall, 1998
The essay which follows reflects the time in which it was
written, a time when “modernism” was going out of fashion, when Andy Warhol was
beginning to be taken seriously, not just as artist, but “philosopher,” and the
“cinema of sight,” associated with the American independent filmmaker Stan Brakhage, had already given way to a “cinema
of intellection,” the so-called “structural film,” which was itself on the
verge of obliteration by our ruthless, trend-obsessed “postmodern”
culture. I attempted to counter the
destructive effects of simplistic modernist and postmodernist dogma alike by
demonstrating that things were not as straightforward as they might seem, that
if Brakhage’s was, indeed, a “cinema of sight,” this meant that “seeing” itself
had to be reconsidered on a very fundamental level indeed, a level that must
take us far beyond the limitations of both Greenbergian modernism and a
“postmodernism” which seemed (and still seems) lost in its own hall of mirrors.
---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
Brakhage's work is, among
students of the film avant‑garde, almost universally acknowledged as
representing a revolutionary break with the past. He is probably the single most influential
(and highly praised) member of the so‑called New American Cinema. Because his work is extremely complex,
difficult to understand and resistant to analysis, however, there is a great
deal of confusion surrounding it.
Aspects of his work (e. g., rapid montage,
painting on film, use of black or clear leader, superimposition, time lapse,
flicker, in-camera editing, jump cuts, hand-held camera -- one could go on and
on) have had enormous impact, certain film makers building entire careers on
the exploration of a single one of his discoveries. His style as a whole, however, has rarely
been imitated with any success. Most who
try, usually enthusiastic beginners, soon grow discouraged by failure to match
his intensity.
Brakhage's style is thought to be entirely
idiosyncratic to him, an attitude that he himself has fostered in his own
writings, especially by the claim that he both shoots and edits his films in a
state approaching trance. So personal,
complex and intense a style strongly discourages followers. The current avant‑garde has taken the hint
and, having plundered his work for ideas and techniques, has moved on,
stylistically, to a world remote from his.
Brakhage
and the Critics
Partly because of the apparently
subjective nature of so many aspects of his films, partly because of attitudes
expressed in his writings, Brakhage has come to be regarded by critics as an
arch‑Romantic, a visionary neo‑idealist.
Annette Michelson's “Camera Lucida Camera Obscura” is a comparison of
Eisenstein and Brakhage, the former “lucida,” the latter “obscura.” Eisenstein
represents the “epic” tradition, shaped ideologically by “dialectical
materialism,” formed artistically by “the poetry, painting and theater which
developed . . . from Futurism through Cubism and Constructivism.” Brakhage
represents the “lyric” tradition, shaped ideologically by “romantic idealism,”
formed artistically “in the movement from the space and conceptual framework of
Cubism through Surrealism to Abstract Expressionism.”[1]
In more or less the same vein, P. Adams Sitney finds in Brakhage, “perhaps more
intensely than anywhere else, the strains of Romantic and post-Romantic poetry
in American art [converging] with the aesthetics of Abstract Expressionism.”[2] Malcom LeGrice, following Sitney's lead,
writes of Brakhage as “epitomizing the direction of personal, visionary cinema,
establishing, more than any other film-maker, the camera as heroic protagonist.
. . Brakhage is primarily an Expressionist,. . . concerned with utilizing
subjective means towards expressing a personal vision . . .”[3]
Brakhage
and Cézanne
An unequivocal refutation of the
prevailing view can be found in the words of Brakhage himself. He has stated, paraphrasing D. W.
Griffith, “all that I really want to do is make you see.” “I wanted to feel like I lived in the same
world with other people. That's not the
same as communicating. . . My primary need was that, at some point, I share a
sight with them. . . I don't think it has much to do with the creative act.”
In the same context, Brakhage describes
himself as “the most thorough documentary film maker in the world because I
document the act of seeing as well as everything that the light brings
me.” Criticizing P. Adams Sitney for
having “no fix on the extent to which I was
documenting,” he complains that Sitney “and many others are still trying
to view me as an imaginative film maker, as an inventor of fantasies or
metaphors.”[4]
Obsession with the “act of seeing”
dominates Brakhage's major theoretical statement, which opens with the following oft-quoted but
little understood passage: “Imagine an eye unruled by manmade laws of
perspective, an eye unprejudiced by compositional logic, an eye which does not
respond to the name of everything but which must know each object encountered
in life through an adventure of perception.
How many colors are there in a field of grass to the crawling baby
unaware of “Green?” How many rainbows can light create for the untutored eye?.
. . Imagine a world before the “beginning was the word.”
Brakhage's evocation of Ruskin's “innocent
eye” has done much to foster his reputation as Romantic anarchist. But he goes beyond Ruskin. Refusing to dwell on the infant's eye, which
soon enough “learns to classify sights,” Brakhage states that “only the
ultimate of knowledge” can compensate for the loss of innocence. Far beyond the naive attempt to subjectively
recreate an Edenic state of pure receptivity is “a pursuit of knowledge foreign
to language and founded upon visual communication, demanding a development of
the optical mind, and dependent upon perception in the original and deepest
sense of the word.”[5]
In evoking a purely sensory “knowledge,”
opposed to the conceptual, Brakhage links Ruskin's theory with the far more
sophisticated project of Cézanne, for whom “optics” meant “a logical vision.”
The process of turning away from conventional, language dominated modes of
seeing, struggling to see with the eyes only, not the mind, a process that
Cézanne attempted to describe sporadically and with great difficulty, is set forth
in Metaphors
on Vision with exhaustive (and exhaustingly confusing) detail. While Brakhage was undoubtedly aware of
Cézanne, there is no question of direct influence. Brakhage was clearly determined, as was the
great painter, to live every detail of the process through his own experience,
taking nothing at second hand. Metaphors
on Vision is, among other things, the kind of document phenomenologist
admirers like Merleau-Ponty would have liked to have had from Cézanne.
Brakhage
and the Apparatus
While, consciously or not, echoing Ruskin and
Cézanne, Metaphors also anticipates Baudry's critique of camera ideology. Contrasting the human eye, “capable of any
imagining” with “the camera eye, its lenses grounded to achieve 19th century
Western compositional perspective,” Brakhage ironically reveals the debt of
motion picture “science” to 19th Century romantic sentimentality. Standardized shutter speeds are “geared
to the feeling of the ideal slow Viennese waltz,” The tripod is “balled with
bearings” to give it a smooth “Les Sylphides motion;” restricted to horizontal
and vertical movements in the spirit of “pillars and horizon lines.” The lens is coated and filtered, the light
meter balanced and the film chemically designed “to provide that picture
postcard effect (salon painting) exemplified by those oh so blue skies and
peachy skins.” Brakhage continues, recommending a host of
“remedies” designed to wrench the apparatus free from perspective and its
attendant rigidities: spitting on the lens, throwing it out of focus, speeding
up or slowing down the shutter, hand-holding, over -- or underexposure, etc.[6]
A
Faceted Vision
If
Metaphors on Vision reveals a truly
dialectical grasp of theory, it reveals also the energy with which Brakhage has
pursued the practice of vision itself.
The following passage demonstrates how the intensity of his
investigations of the act of seeing brings him to the point of Cubist fragmentation:
“concentrated once upon my wife's arm, elbow to hand, my eyes drew every
possible line out of it until all seemed strands separated as if in a
dissection of its light and shadow surface.
Then a semi-reformation produced multiple arms, moving independently in
this re-defined space, superimposing over each other, all differently drawn. .
. Eventually it became impossible for me to discern the originating image.”
If we see the “multiple arms, moving
independently” each in its own fragment of
time, as a series of very brief
shots, we have something very close to one aspect of Brakhage's montage. Rapid montage is, of course, the strongest
and most pervasive aspect of Brakhage's mature style. Taken in itself, it can be regarded as both
the most and the least original feature of that style. At the time of its emergence in his work (the
late Fifties) montage of this sort was considered completely outdated, a brave
experiment that had failed; it was no longer “being done.” The novelty of Brakhage's montage was
therefore enhanced by the almost total eclipse of the Russian masters who, as
he readily admits, had influenced him.
Nevertheless, a single viewing of a film
like Brakhage's Anticipation of the Night, his first really ambitious venture in
rapid montage, will reveal beyond any doubt the enormous gulf between his
approach and that of his predecessors.
Although this film has been paraphrased by Brakhage in
narrative-symbolic terms, none of this is in any way reinforced by any of the
elements of film language or rhetoric pioneered by the early montage masters.
The result is extremely confusing, even
after several viewings. There is an
avalanche of shots, shots of shadows, of trees, of the sun, of water of grass. Many of these are blurred by very rapid
camera movements, often to the point that we cannot “read” any image at
all. Even when we can read the images,
nothing seems to hang together in any of the ways that we have learned to
expect from our previous experience with montage.
Brakhage's time facets, like the
“exploded” spatial facets of late analytic Cubism, break down continuity much
more radically than anything in Eisenstein, Vertov, Gance or Leger. Time seems to be starting and stopping anew
with each shot, which refuses to “link up,” conceptually, with its
neighbors. There is no sense of a time
“container” within which a single coherent event might occur.
“Expressionist”
Spaces
Analysis of films like this has proven a
tremendous stumbling block for critics.
The simple observation that Brakhage has thrown conventional narrative
overboard, while certainly true, is only a beginning. Many critics rest content with haphazard descriptions
of particular techniques, reserving most of their powers to the piecing
together of some sort of more or less reasonable quasi-narrative exegesis.
Writers with some background in modernist
art invariably make a special point of Brakhage's treatment of
screen-space. According to the
prevailing wisdom, modernism has something to do with the flattening of space;
much of Brakhage's camera work has the effect of flattening space; ergo,
Brakhage is a modernist. Moreover, the
spatial effect of Brakhage's images, so often vague, blurry, distorted, even
messy, easily calls to mind the treatment of space so characteristic of certain
Abstract Expressionist painters, particularly Pollock and de Kooning. Given the historical situation, coupled with
the apparently subjective tone of Brakhage's own writings, it is not difficult
to see why his work is almost always discussed within the context of Abstract
Expressionist esthetics.
Analysis of this sort does make sense, as far as it goes. Brakhage's esthetic has undoubtedly been
deeply touched by Abstract Expressionism.
The influence has been most obvious in his handling of the camera,
almost always a matter of spontaneous, unpremeditated involvement, akin to “action
painting.” Everything in the workings of
the apparatus designed to give a neat, orderly spatial impression in depth is
strongly resisted. True to his written
testimony, he has spat on the lens, thrown it out of focus, jiggled the camera. He has resisted the all too easy tendency of
the lens to generate automatic perspective space in a hundred ways, from the
use of distorting lenses to emphasis on extreme close-ups.
Editing
and Spontaneity
While Brakhage's “expressionist” treatment
of screen-space is an undeniable aspect of his style, analysis in terms of
space alone can be of little use in the effort to grasp his far more
characteristic and consistent approach to montage. There is, moreover, really nothing in
Abstract Expressionist esthetics to prepare one for the situation encountered
in the editing room. Here, no matter how
spontaneous one might like to be, the laborious process of locating specific
pieces of film, deciding where each will fit and precisely how long it will be,
invariably demands a certain amount of conscious, even calculated decision
making.
While much has been made of Brakhage's
experimentation with films edited in the camera, the great majority of his
major works involve enormous amounts of
post-facto editing. This indeed
is usually the stage where various pieces of footage, often shot with no
particular “final product” in mind, are brought together and the film as such
takes shape. This “analytic” process,
often involving laboriously detailed notes and sketches, is deliberately
omitted by certain film makers, influenced by Brakhage, whose work can much
more successfully be identified with Abstract Expressionism: Andrew Noren, Werner Nekes and Paul Winkler,
among others.
Screen-Space
vs. Time
Over and above the issue of “Abstract
Expressionist spontaneity” is the basic issue of space vs. time in film.
As I have already argued [in an earlier chapter], treatment of
screen-space is much less of a problem in film generally than treatment of
time. Only the time-producing space of
the film strip itself can, after all, be regarded as the ground of film syntax,
positive or negative. Screen-space is highly flexible --
idiosyncratic spaces do not need to be reconciled, as in a painting, since they
can readily be replaced.
Idiosyncratic events must, on the
other hand, take their place as permanently determined elements of the time
field.
Film, moreover, is not a particularly
plastic medium in its spatial dimension.
As with photography generally, there has been a considerable sacrifice
of plasticity to the rigid optics of “realism.”
Outside the realm of animation, precise spatial facetting in film would
be extraordinarily difficult. Stratagems
such as spitting on the lens or shaking the camera, while effective in
neutralizing certain built-in effects, can hardly be taken seriously as
attempts at spatial determination. Film
is precise exactly where it most needs to be -- in time.
“Cubist”
Time
The essential structural element in
Brakhage's work is the precisely controlled temporal discontinuity of his
montage, directly analogous to the precise spatial discontinuities of
Cubism. Unlike Eisenstein, Brakhage does
not compromise in order to preserve the sense of a coherent, even partially
continuous time field. There is rarely
any attempt to correlate the shot to shot sequences as edited with some kind of
“normal” sequence of events, either narrative or documentary.
On the contrary, techniques which defeat
“positive” temporal continuity are liberally employed: jump cuts, both forward and backward in time;
immediate repetition of similar shots; recurrence of similar shots at various,
often widely separated parts of the film; the use of “rhythmic” montage; shot
to shot variation of movement-tempo and direction of movement; extreme fragmentation
of the time field through rapid cutting.
Sound, traditionally a powerful reinforcer of continuity, is eliminated.
Plastic Cutting
The meaning of Brakhage's montage vis a vis continuity and discontinuity,
Abstract Expressionism and Cubism, is far from obvious. We can, in fact, go more deeply into both
issues by pursuing a revealing, if quite natural, misunderstanding. I have already had occasion to cite Annette
Michelson's “Camera Lucida Camera Obscura,” where she associates Eisenstein with
Cubism and Brakhage with Abstract Expressionism. Toward the end of this article, she sums up
an aspect of their relationship as follows: “If Eisenstein's cinema of
intellection depends upon the unity of the disjunct, sensed as disjunct, the
cinema of sight [Brakhage's cinema] will be, from this point on [since Anticipation of the Night], incomparably
fluid.” A bit later, writing of Anticipation of the Night, she clarifies
as follows: “Its fluidity almost belies its total sovereignty. The cuts are many and quick . . . but -- and
this is Brakhage's point of dialectical intensity -- they are fused by a camera
movement sustained over cuts. Disparate
images . . . are united by movement or direction either repeated or sustained
through the cut. Disparate spaces are
unified in a consistent flattening or obscuring of spatial coordinates and that
unity is intensified by the synthetic effect of continuous movement produced in
editing.”[7]
Anyone familiar with Brakhage's work will
recognize in the above a description of what he has called “plastic
cutting.” Defined by P. Adams Sitney as “the joining of shots at
points of movement, close-up or abstraction to soften the brunt of montage,”
plastic cutting is a pervasive element of Brakhage's approach to editing which
can take many forms: he may cut from a shot which ends in black to one which
begins in black; or from white to white; he may cut from movement to movement
or blur to blur so that, in the confusion, the exact time point of the cut is
obscured; he may match the shape of one part of an image with a similar shape
in the same part of the frame in the next shot; he may superimpose film rolls
so that cuts on one are masked by bright or dark areas on another; he may
combine any of the above.
While all forms of plastic cutting tend to
fuse juxtaposed shots, contrasting such fusions with the disjunctions of
Cubism, as Michelson does, is a fundamental error. Plastic cutting is, in fact, closely
analogous with Cubist passage. The
connection will be more evident if we backtrack a bit to our earlier discussion
[in an earlier chapter] of positive montage.
Passage in Conventional Montage
As was then pointed out,
devices such as cutting on motion (the
match cut), and the dissolve are
temporal reconciliations of a kind very similar to the spatial reconciliations
of passage as found in the paintings and drawings of the “old masters.” Like their spatial counterparts, these filmic
devices contain the seeds of radical disjunction since they take place, not in
representational time, but on the “surface time” of the film strip. Because such a time field has no
representational meaning, the viewer interprets its emergence as a “warping” of
the time “ground” enclosing the time “figures,” the events; hence the
interpretation of the dissolve as “passage (really distortion) of time.”
Cutting on motion is a bit more
subtle. Nevertheless, in distracting the
viewer momentarily from motion contained in representational time to uncontained motion “in itself,” carried over
from one shot to the next, the match cut
sets up a tiny kinetic “charge” of
“surface time.” When, as in less
conventional films, cutting on motion is used more agressively to link two
ordinarily unrelated motions (e. g., the swinging of a tennis racquet and the
lurching of an automobile) its artificial, purely formal invocation of the
filmic “surface” is more pronounced.
Such an effect is often used as a “sophisticated” substitute for the
dissolve. Other, closely related effects
are produced in what is called “associational editing,” a famous example being
the well-known transition from scream to railroad whistle. Again the viewer is distracted momentarily by
a purely formal link on the “temporal surface.”
Plastic
Cutting As “Cubist” Passage
All of the above devices verge on the
subliminal, having, like “old master” passage in painting, traditionally been
treated with great restraint and a host of taboos. Brakhage's plastic cutting, in the spirit of Cubist
passage, agressively violates the taboos. Extreme intensification of the transitional
negates its original function, transforming “old master” and even Cezannian
reconciliation into Cubistic disjunction.
Where a professional editor will, when cutting on motion, take great care to preserve the sense of representational time-flow, Brakhage will deliberately disrupt it. Through plastic editing, for example, the motion of a person's head turning to screen left may be completed by automobile headlights turning in the same direction. A zoom-in on the headlights may “become” a child's face rushing toward the camera. These motions have nothing in common as far as representational time is concerned -- the flow from one to the other cannot be contained within it.
On the contrary, the fusion of any two
motions in this manner calls forth the otherwise subliminal temporal “surface,”
which, like the pictorial surface of Cubism, causes juxtaposed representational
elements to repel one another. Paradoxically, therefore, it is through the
fluidities of plastic editing that Brakhage most completely resists the fusion
of his images into conceptually manageable perceptions. [As should be clear at this point, the word
“surface” has become problematic. Like
Derrida’s “writing,” or “trace,” words which should by no means be taken at
face value, “surface” in the context of Cubism or of Brakhage’s mature films
has become “difficult” and should not too easily be “understood.” In terms of the theoretical construct I am
erecting here, the term ultimately merges with the “negative field” itself,
thereby losing all connection with the notion of surface as usually understood,
in the sense of some sort of tangible “material substance.”]
Michelson has oversimplified by failing to
recognize the dual function of Brakhage's fluidities. Eisenstein's clear cut fragmentations, like
those of the Futurists, fail to generate the strong negative field which alone
can prevent them from reuniting within a heightened positivity. His straightforward “collisions” simply
generate a more highly charged “current” of positive syntax through which the
narrative may more dramatically flow.
Brakhage's fluidities, on the other hand, literally “short circuit” this
current, fully opening forbidden channels.
Motion
And Stasis
It is hardly an accident that so much of
the preceding has hinged on Brakhage's treatment of motion. Unlike Eisenstein, who preferred to juxtapose
essentially static shots, Brakhage typically places great emphasis on mobility
within the shot, to the extent that some of his films seem in perpetual
motion. Even when his subject is not
moving, his camera usually is, often violently so. This intensive, highly original and varied
use of motion is extremely problematic, generating results that are often
contradictory, as we have seen. In order
to understand it, we must probe more deeply the nature of the cinematic
apparatus and its effects.
If film can be described as in some sense
uniting time and space, its capacity to generate motion (or the illusion
thereof) is the most dramatic evidence of this union. Motion can, in fact, be regarded as a kind of passage uniting the two fields. At the same time it can be said to generate a
somewhat independent secondary “field” of its own. In this respect, motion must be considered in
relation to its opposite, stasis. In
gestalt terms, motion can be considered as a “figure” seen within the “ground”
of stasis.
As with the background space of positive
pictorial syntax, the stasis of positive filmic syntax operates as an
invisible, abstract field, a temporal container within which motion takes
place. In conventional film, the viewer
must never be in doubt as to which is which.
This is by no means as simple as it seems, for either the camera or the
photographed object or both may originally have been moving. If the object is to be perceived as moving,
the camera must be perceived as a stable ground. If the camera is to be seen as moving (as in
a wide angle horizontal pan), the image (a landscape, say) must be seen as
ground. If camera and object are both
perceived as moving, “figure-ground” stability is in danger of breaking down altogether
-- often there is some other element on the screen which must be read as
stable.
Motion figure-ground can lead to illusions
as powerful as any associated with perspective.
For example, in a typical pan, say from left to right, we might see a
group of buildings literally moving across the screen from right to left. If, as is usually the case, we read the
buildings as stable, the screen itself must take on the motion and appear to
move from left to right. The mind of the
viewer is able, with no trouble at all, to accept this impossible situation by
creating an unseen element, what we may call the “omniscient viewer,” an all
seeing Godlike eye. When, according to
the logic of motion figure-ground, the screen (the camera) must appear to move,
this movement is understood as movement of the “omniscient viewer.” The image of buildings drifting right to left
across the screen thus becomes the left to right motion of the “omniscient
viewer's” head as it scans the horizon.
Negative Motion
Through his characteristic use of the camera
(coupled with plastic editing), Brakhage tends to destroy the figure-ground
relations of conventional film motion.
One might say that his extreme camera movements and his tendency to cut
on movement generate a “negative” motion, analogous to negative time and space.
For instance, Brakhage's version of the
pan described above might well be extremely rapid and irregular, with a sudden
downward tilt of the camera at the end, so that the buildings lurch upward. This upward motion might be continued in the
next shot by, say, a flock of birds rising out of a tree. As most beginners know, a too rapid
horizontal pan in itself can radically disrupt our normal manner of perceiving
motion. This, coupled with its
irregularity and the sudden lurch at the end, would make it all but impossible
to read in terms of an “omniscient viewer.”
Any tendency to interpret the upward lurch of the buildings as the
secondary result of a downward movement of such a viewer's head (or even
“realistically” in terms of camera movement), would be seriously weakened by
the continuation of the upward flow in the “primary” motion of the birds. As any two motions fuse through plastic
editing, it becomes exceedingly difficult to “read” each as having an
independent source.
In such a context all motions will tend
to be seen simply as movement of images across the screen. If an image is moving from screen right to
left, we will not tend to read it as the stable “ground” of some inferred movement
from left to right (such as that of an “omniscient viewer”) but will be more or
less forced to accept it as right-left movement “in itself.” Thus, in his radical complication of motion,
Brakhage induces us to simplify our means of comprehending it.[8]
That our analysis of negative motion is
still incomplete, however, will be evident if we ask ourselves what it means to
say that “an image is moving from screen right to left.” No thing is actually moving across the screen,
only something we call an “image.” The
cinematic image, as we know, is the result of light projected through a
photographic emulsion which either lets it pass or, to some extent, interrupts
it. This play of light and shadow is
clearly visible as such in the space between projector and screen (given a
certain amount of dust and/or smoke in the screening area). Lifting our eyes to study this space, we can
appreciate how the notion of cinematic movement “in itself” is intimately tied
to the formation of a “readable” image which must function as a “figure” of
motion. In the absence of such an image,
our eyes removed from the screen to the space directly overhead, we see that
motion of light in one direction is equivalent to motion of shadow in the
opposite direction. Placing our attention
on one, we may see motion from right to left; shifting our attention to the
other, all else being equal, motion is suddenly from left to right.
Brakhage's tendency to weaken the figural
impact of the image (through out-of-focus photography, spitting on the lens,
etc.), coupled with his radical complication of motion (as described above)
often does, indeed, lead to effects of just this kind, not just in the space
overhead, but on the screen itself. In
such instances, all sense of motion figure-ground can collapse, motion
literally dissolving with the image itself into a play of light and
shadow. What we see may be changing but
is not moving. Thus in their most
extreme violence, Brakhage's motions can lead to stasis.
As should now be evident, the entire
dialectic of film motion and stasis parallels that of pictorial figure and
ground in the movement from perspective space to Cubism. In each case, as the “negative” asserts
itself, the passive background comes forward.
Stasis, as the “background” against which motion is perceived is, in all
traditional films, simply weightless and invisible, like the ground of
pictorial positive syntax. When, with
Brakhage, the figure-ground of positive cinematic motion is weakened, the
ground, or “negative” of motion asserts itself.
In its weaker form, this “negative motion” can cause us to perceive the
simple “surface” motion of the image across the screen rather than the implied
motion, in the opposite direction, of an “omniscient viewer.” In its stronger form, it reveals itself not
simply as the negative of any particular direction of motion but of motion itself:
negative motion is stasis made
visible, analogous to the Cubist pictorial surface, made visible through the
assertion of negative space.
But what can it mean to say “stasis made
visible?” How can one equate an abstract
concept with something concrete, like a pictorial surface? Once again, we must return to our basic
analogy: as a pictorial figure presented against a ground is equivalent to a
form seen within passive space, filmic motion presented against stasis is
equivalent to an event perceived within passive
time. Stasis, is, in fact,
equivalent to what we have been calling time.
As negative pictorial syntax brings space actively forward as a
concretely perceptible surface, so negative film syntax brings time (stasis)
forward in a similar way. Thus, in
Brakhage, time is perceived largely in its own terms, as specific “weighted”
duration, rather than in terms of some motion contained in it, which can
only imply
its existence. Duration in this sense
can, ultimately, be determined only in terms of the linear space of the film
strip itself, that array of totally static images on which cinematic negative
motion, negative time and stasis ultimately find identity and concrete
existence.
Thus has Brakhage written of creating his
films “with an eye to their speaking just as strips of celluloid held in the
hand . . .,” stating that “all my significant splices . . . are the result of
viewing the film to be edited both through the editor at an approximate 24
frames a second and also as stilled strips of film . . .”[9] [In an earlier chapter of my book, I
discuss, at some length, Bergson’s notion of duration, as opposed to what he
calls “cinematographic time.” Brakhage’s
approach to montage is at once a subversion of
“cinematographic time,” an affirmation of Bergson’s “duration,” a refutation
of Bergon’s critique of “the spatialization of time,” and a demonstration of
what Derrida might mean by “spacing” as “temporization.”]
Resisting
The Conceptual Order
As the above analysis demonstrates,
Brakhage's compositional “strategies” involve the complete dismantling of
cinematic positive syntax, from the intricacies of montage language and
perspective time all the way down to the fundamental “denial of difference”
[see reference to Jean Louis Baudry in the Preface] which is the illusion of
motion itself. While it would undoubtedly
be misleading and in any case grossly anachronistic to characterize Brakhage as
a “Cubist” film maker, our theoretical framework clearly reveals a profound
structural affinity between his strategies and those of Cubism.
Most obvious, of course, is the parallel
between Cubist facetting and rapid montage.
More fundamental is the analogous treatment of the syntactic field
generally. As with Cubist passage, Brakhage's plastic cutting
simultaneously breaks up the overall field of representation (positive time)
and unites the various micro-fields (the individual shots) on the “surface”
(the negative time field generated by the film strip -- fundamentally, the film
strip itself).
As the negative space of Cubism destroys
depth, Brakhage's negative time (and negative motion) destroys time
“depth.” Each moment tends to become
static and isolated, an event unto itself, freed from dependence on past and
future, experienced as a unique time of its own. As in Cubism, negative determination of the
perceptual field is equivalent to the disruption of positive syntax -- negative
time is negative syntax. Each image is
thus isolated within its own static micro-time as each painted “sign” becomes
isolated within Cubist space. Union of
and on the surface becomes representational (and perceptual) disjunction. [From my present perspective, I must admit
that the preceding paragraph contains passages which oversimplify an
extraordinarily complex and subtle issue.
There is always a danger, in such characterizations, of reconstituting “the present moment” as some
sort of absolutely privileged, mystical,
transcendence of time and space, whereas what I am trying to express is
something very different, something in a sense almost directly opposed to this,
the “moment” experienced as radically contingent, radically “ordinary,”
radically localized, radically ephemeral, “static and isolated” in its passing, its ephemerality. What is being “named” here is, ultimately,
un-nameable.]
While Abstract Expressionism lays positive
syntax aside and simply affirms the
surface, the negative syntax of Brakhage and the Cubists actively engages
positive syntax in a struggle for the surface.
Without such a struggle, as has already been emphasized, the “context of
implication” will arise from the ashes of positive syntax, giving birth to
ambiguity and its attendent mystifications.
[The “context of implication,” related to Freud’s notion of “secondary elaboration,” Jakobson’s notion of metonymic structure, and Bataille’s informe, can be understood as a kind of “proto-syntax” in which all kinds of loosely
or even randomly juxtaposed elements can come together ambiguously or
polysemically to make some sort of sense even when no clearly defined syntactic
field is present.]
In Brakhage, for the first time in the
history of film, the context of implication itself is consistently encountered
and disrupted. As a result, his images,
as images, appear with a unique clarity -- even the blurred images, seen as blurred, are vividly clear. Despite the fact that the film maker has done
nothing to help the viewer “get” the ideas “behind” the film, there is no
feeling of ambiguity [or polysemy] in the usual sense.
We may certainly be confused when watching
a Brakhage film -- we will not be led to
believe that everything we see implies something else, that when two images are
juxtaposed in time this is more than a “mere” juxtaposition, that there is some
relationship between them, clear or ambiguous, which must, as, for example, in
the Kuleshov experiment, be revealed in our “imagination.” It is this ability to create juxtapositions
which resist our need for what Rosalind Krauss has called a “conceptual order.
. . transcending the materials of experience,”[10]
that is the true achievement of Brakhage's montage, the heart of his cinematic
revolution.
The
Link With Realism
The preceding discussion, necessarily
highly formal, might lead one to conclude that Brakhage's films are, indeed,
totally formal structures, presentations of isolated bits of time or film
completely devoid of significant connections with any outer or inner
reality. Such a conclusion would be
totally inadequate, a crude simplification of an extraordinarily rich and
complex creative nexus. Brakhage's films
are strongly rooted in the deepest possible involvement with the outer and
inner worlds and the relation between them.
Turning first to the former, I have
already cited his view of himself as fundamentally a documentor, a view
reinforced by much in Metaphors on Vision. As our transition from the naturalist
viewpoints expressed in this work to the “Cubistic” organization of the films
themselves was rather abrupt, the link with realism may have depended too much
on the purely theoretical analogies involved.
Now that the theoretical points have been made, let us, for the sake of
argument, lay them aside to ask ourselves a very basic, practical question
which goes to the heart of realism: how
can we best present an ordinary event filmically in such a way that it is
perceived as much as possible in and for itself (rather than in terms of
something else) with maximum clarity and minimum distortion?
We could, of course, film it cinema verite style, in a single long
take. Let us even assume that we could
accomplish this in a manner that did not evoke any of the overtones of film
language. What would such a procedure
accomplish? Upon careful examination, we
would discover that our long take of an “event” actually consisted of a myriad
of shorter events, all running into one another. A long take is, in time, what a wide angle
shot is in space. We get a total picture
but lose all sense of detail. If we are
serious about clarity, we must concern ourselves with detail. Let us therefore redefine “event” as a
relatively brief occurrence which can be fully grasped in a single act of
perception. In order to do justice to
this detail, we must somehow isolate it from the surrounding events.
Within a long take, a single event can be
isolated by zooming in on it. If the
cameraperson failed to zoom, the effect can be produced on an optical printer. The sudden, close-up view will, indeed,
enhance clarity and detail; it will also unavoidably call forth overtones of
film language. The detail will, in fact,
lose its “ordinariness.” Singled out in this manner, it will be “read” as
having a special significance, a veiled meaning in terms of some context not
yet completely clear.
We could go farther, taking the event
completely out of context by literally cutting it out of the long take,
attaching head leader, tail leader, and rather clinically, projecting it as a
totally isolated shot. In the abstract,
this might seem reasonable. In practice,
it would be extremely difficult to properly prepare viewers for what they are
about to see. After an indefinite length
of time during which blank leader is on the screen, the shot would suddenly
appear. If truly brief, it could well be
over before the viewers realized it had begun.
An obvious solution to the above problem
might be to project the shot in slow motion.
This would give viewers time to adjust to the shot's appearance; it
would also enhance certain details. The
value of slow motion with respect to detail has indeed been so highly touted
that its one serious drawback is rarely mentioned: it involves a distortion of
the time field. Perceiving an event in
slow motion, we cannot grasp it as it happened in its own characteristic tempo --
its inherent evanescence, the special
kind of clarity made possible by the vivid apprehension of a brief moment,
would be lost.
Splicing the head of the clip to its tail,
we could make a loop which could be repeated indefinitely. The many repetitions would enable viewers to
grasp a good amount of detail without the need for slow motion. However, such a recourse would still involve
serious drawbacks: by being repeated, the event would be overemphasized, losing
its special quality as something unique; such repetition can very quickly
induce viewer fatigue and/or something like a trance state, hardly conducive to
clear perception; finally, repetition will invariably call attention to itself -- viewers will tend to see the form, the repetition, rather than its
content, the event.
The nature of the problem should, at this
point, be reasonably clear. There would
seem to be no way to simply and/or systematically achieve what has to be one of
the fundamental requirements of film realism, the clear presentation of an
ordinary event in its own terms, within its own time frame. Sensitive to this basic difficulty, Brakhage,
like Cézanne, realized that the problem of clear seeing in itself called forth
a complex, highly intuitive process of active vision.
In the spirit of Cézanne and the
Cubists, he set out to place each event within a context of similar events, a
context specifically created, composed
so that each would set the other off, with none dominating. Only through an actively determined, complex
composition of this sort, in which each event can be apprehended in its own
unique evanescence, set off by, but not confused with or dominated by
neighboring events, can we hope to achieve realism in any rigorous sense. The struggle for perception on this level,
with each thing seen in and for its own uniqueness, rather than as a part of
some larger, transcendent “reality,” is only another way of describing what I
have called “negative montage.” Thus everything
already discussed on the formal level has roots deep within the soil of the
realist quest.
We may, at this point, return to the
passage from Erwin Panofsky, quoted in chapter 2. It will be recalled that Panofsky referred to
the “idealistic conception of the world” implied in “all the representational
arts,” a conception causing them to “operate from top to bottom,” starting with
“an idea. . . not with the objects that constitute the physical world.” According to Panofsky, only “the movies”
operate in the other direction, from “bottom to top,” thus doing “justice to
that materialistic interpretation of the universe which. . . pervades
contemporary civilization.”
As our discussion of ideology [see
discussion of Baudry, in the Preface] has made clear, such a statement can only
be taken as representing a potential state of affairs, not something simply
given through use of the motion picture camera [and related technology --
Baudry’s “apparatus”], as Panofsky implies.
Not, in fact, until we reach the mature work of Brakhage is the promise
of a true film realism along materialist lines fulfilled.
In his films we are, for the first time,
completely freed from the domination of the “idea,” either, as in narrative,
“Russian” Montage and much experimental film, explicitly present as a
structural and interpretive force or, as in
Cinema Verite, implicitly present as a conventionalized constraint on
vision itself through dependence on the apparatus and its ideology. Through development of the complex
interactive process that I have called “negative montage,” Brakhage has been
able to free both the “material” of everyday life and the “material” of film
itself from the necessity for conceptual mediation, liberating them from
systematic control to speak, essentially, for themselves. Thus, not simply through manipulation of a
technical device, but by means of a creative accomplishment of considerable
scope, Brakhage's films finally do illuminate that infinitely rich “bottom” of
which Panofsky speaks.
The
Associative Nexus
Having addressed the problem of Brakhage's
link with the outer world, I must now speak to his relation with the
inner. No aspect of his work has been so
fully discussed, yet so often misunderstood, as his apparently fanatical
absorbtion in the “mythic” aspects of his own life and personality. This extraordinarily intense inner quest has,
understandably, generated a good deal of skepticism regarding his claims as a
“documentarist.”
Unquestionably, Brakhage's earliest
cinematic impulses stemmed from a deep need for self-exploration. When he began making films in the early
Fifties, the prevailing mode of American cinematic experimentalism was what
P. Adams Sitney has called the “trance”
film. For Brakhage, as for his mentors
(among the most prominent, Maya Deren, James Broughton and Kenneth Anger), the
trance film, essentially a created film-dream, was a means of self-analysis
very much in the spirit of Freud.
Indeed, as Sitney has written, “Freud has never meant as much to any
other film-maker” as to Brakhage,[11]
whose relation to psychoanalysis rivals Eisenstein's to dialectical
materialism. Another influence, equally
popular among the intellectuals of the period, was Surrealism, itself heavily
in debt to Freud.
Central to both psychoanalytic and Surrealist
“technique” is a process known as “free-association,” a means of short
circuiting the convention-bound workings of the rational mind in order to reach
the unconscious. In free-association, as
in Surrealist “automatic writing,” the subject is encouraged to develop word
associations devoid of either syntactic connection or consciously derived
symbolism. One simply speaks or writes
the “first thing” that comes into ones mind.
Few artists have applied free-association
so rigorously to every aspect of their work as has Brakhage. His determination to “turn off” the workings
of the conscious mind is, indeed, his closest link with Abstract Expressionist
painting, itself born from a similar mix of Surrealism and Freud. While free-association is used rather timidly
in the early trance films, largely as a source of “plot” elements, the later
films draw on it far more intensely as a guide to camera work and montage.
In psychoanalysis, the analyst uses the
patient's free associations as a guide to help sort out the “inner meaning” of
dreams and fantasies which are presumed to stand for “censored” unconscious
thoughts. Brakhage has often written of
his own films as though he himself were the “analyst,” struggling to reach the
hidden depths symbolized within.
Following his lead, most commentators have adopted a similar strategy,
treating his films as dreams to be explicated in symbolic terms.
While interpretations of this sort can be
highly relevant and revealing, as with psychoanalysis itself, too much
dependence on associative symbolization can lead to endless and pointless
ambiguities. In therapy, the
justification for any given method is its promise of a cure -- what justifies
any particular method of filmic interpretation? The “totalizing end” of
Brakhage's film, Dog Star Man, for P.
Adams Sitney, an outstanding Brakhage explicator, is not what it is for
Brakhage himself. To Sitney, the climax
comes with the image of the Dog Star Man furiously chopping the tree, a
chopping which “becomes a metaphor for the splicing of film.” According to Sitney, “the apotheosis which
Brakhage describes (Dog Star Man assuming Cassiopeia's throne in the sky)
appears for but a second on the screen and it is not the last image of that
figure. We see him furiously chopping
again. . .”[12]
In the absence of any theoretical
framework above and beyond Sitney's vague allusions to Blake and the Romantics,
there is no meaningful basis for choosing either version or for assuming that
the film has an “apotheosis” at all. In
view of the fact that Brakhage very definitely does employ free-association,
the sensitivity to its workings undoubtedly displayed by commentators like
Sitney has genuine value. In the last
analysis, however, such commentary, even by Brakhage himself, is tentative at
best and all too often misleading.
The
Pitfalls of Paraphrase
The heart of the difficulty with symbolic
paraphrase of a mature Brakhage film is the extremely problematic relation
between free association, conventional film language and negative syntax. Brakhage's films are more than
associationally determined strings of imagery.
Not only do they put aside the conventions of film language, they
actively oppose such conventions. What is more, if our analysis is correct,
they oppose the implicational context which permits any sort of symbolism, even
of the most unconventional kind, to arise.
While many Brakhage commentators reveal some awareness of the above, the
great majority proceed as though the distinctions involved did not somehow
really matter.
As an example, let us remain with Sitney,
whose interpretations are so insightful as to be all the more misleading. For Sitney, Brakhage's The
Animals of Eden and After “portrays the process of convalescence as a
normalization or accommodation to socially dictated patterns of perception and
thought.” Describing the turning point
of the film as the birth of a goat, he characterizes this event as the point,
“within the narrative of the film, . . . at which the child, [the film's
“protagonist”] witnessing the birth of the animal, imagines his own
birth.” At another point Brakhage
“intercuts [a] caged bird with the crying child. . . The trapped bird now
stands for the feeling of the weeping child.”[13]
The difficulties of this kind of exegesis
are immediately apparent upon a viewing of the film. As with most Brakhage works we are presented
with a barrage of disjunct images linked by no trace of film language;
organized, as I have already stressed, in such a way as to defeat any possible
coding process before it can begin. We
see images of a young boy in bed. Nothing
in the film informs us that he is the protagonist of a narrative. We see a goat giving birth, but there is
nothing in the way this event presents itself that can lead us to understand it
as a “turning point.” If a shot of the
boy directly follows a shot of the goat, it is Brakhage's special achievement,
all but unique among filmmakers, that we will not fall victim to the Kuleshov effect and automatically assume
that the child is “witnessing the birth” of a baby goat. Similarly, a juxtaposition of a shot of “the crying child” and the caged bird cannot,
in the context created by Brakhage, cause the bird to “stand for the feeling of
the weeping child.” If Sitney's
interpretation were as straightforwardly accurate as his presentation implies,
he would be describing something completely conventional, an episode from The Waltons, perhaps.
A clue to what is going on in the above
“reading” is provided by the Freudian context to which I have already
alluded. Sitney is reading, probably
with genuine insight, not the film, but the nexus of associations behind it,
associations which have left their trace upon the film itself as though it were
a dream. The object of analysis,
therefore, is not Animals of Eden and After but Brakhage himself. As a series of insights into Brakhage's state
of mind, projected onto the images of the sick child, Sitney's analysis is
unquestionably valuable. In failing to
distinguish between the film itself and the associations surrounding it,
however, he makes the fatal mistake of treating the later work as though it
were still at the “trance film” stage, a series of symbolic film-dreams. In settling for a “dream analysis,” in which
Brakhage's overriding concern with the destruction of conceptually determined
vision is treated “metaphorically,” Sitney leads his readers away from the
struggle, so apparent in the films themselves, for the real thing.
[Already when I first wrote this, as I was very much aware, it was a commonplace to insist that “one cannot” separate out “the work itself” from the associations surrounding it, that there can be no “work itself” apart from such associations and certainly no “real thing” as opposed to something mediated by language, culture, politics, etc. For almost every other body of cinematic work, I would heartily agree, but in Brakhage’s case, I must vigorously dissent. Not that I see Brakhage in terms of the rightfully discredited notion of the “autonomous” work of art, promoted by Clement Greenberg and some of his more idealist colleagues. But in Brakhage, as in the Cubism of Braque and Picasso and the work of certain other modernists, something very different is afoot and must be thought differently. Personal associations are obviously still extremely important for such artists, but, at the very heart of their work, there is a profound dissociation between the work itself and the personal meanings and feelings which gave rise to it. Such works, as I argue in a later chapter of my book, are more comparable to psychoanalysis itself than to anything that could possibly be analyzed by it.]
[Already when I first wrote this, as I was very much aware, it was a commonplace to insist that “one cannot” separate out “the work itself” from the associations surrounding it, that there can be no “work itself” apart from such associations and certainly no “real thing” as opposed to something mediated by language, culture, politics, etc. For almost every other body of cinematic work, I would heartily agree, but in Brakhage’s case, I must vigorously dissent. Not that I see Brakhage in terms of the rightfully discredited notion of the “autonomous” work of art, promoted by Clement Greenberg and some of his more idealist colleagues. But in Brakhage, as in the Cubism of Braque and Picasso and the work of certain other modernists, something very different is afoot and must be thought differently. Personal associations are obviously still extremely important for such artists, but, at the very heart of their work, there is a profound dissociation between the work itself and the personal meanings and feelings which gave rise to it. Such works, as I argue in a later chapter of my book, are more comparable to psychoanalysis itself than to anything that could possibly be analyzed by it.]
A patient in the hands of a psychoanalyst
may well be doomed indefinitely to the ambiguities of free-association. An artist can go beyond this stage to work
precisely and unambiguously within the formal possibilities of a particular
medium. In wedding his highly original
formal strategies to an essentially derivative but deeply felt involvement with
associationally determined subject matter, Brakhage has employed the former to
clarify the latter, bringing it up out of the obscure realm of dream, “visionary”
experience, and “poetic” ambiguity, into the clear light of organized
“ordinary” vision.
In the extraordinarily complex films which
result, ambiguity is “resolved” into something with which it can easily be
confused, a rarely achieved mode of perception which provides the key to
Brakhage's relation with his subject matter.
Let us call it by the self-descriptive, if somewhat awkward, term,
“multi-referentiality.”
Ambiguity and multi-referentiality represent different
stages in the evolutionary process leading from naive realism to negative
syntax. The contradictions of realism
first manifest themselves as ambiguities, of vision, representation, or
both. Two or more interpretations
present themselves in a context (the context of implication) which demands
resolution on some “higher” level. As no
such level is perceptually evident, it is inferred in the realm of
“meaning.” A vague aura of mystery
arises through the contemplation of some level of “inner meaning” on which such
seemingly disjunct elements can be unified.
As the ambiguities become more intense, the explanations in terms of
“inner meaning” become more farfetched.
Thus do the extreme ambiguities of Cubism call forth speculations
regarding the “fourth dimension.” As the
apparently strange and mysterious spaces of Cubism resolve on the
matter-of-fact surface, so do its ambiguities give way to multi-referentiality. In this context, there is no sense of implication,
no paradox that must be resolved within some higher or broader field which
might encompass it. A passively
“aesthetic” sense of awe in the face of deep, impenetrable mystery, is replaced
by an active struggle to see and understand purely on the basis of what is directly perceptible and thinkable. Whatever one may conclude remains open to
revision, rethinking, relooking.
True multi-referentiality is extremely
rare and represents a profound achievement, enabling both artist and involved
viewer to come to terms with what is presented to the eye and mind on many
different levels, each with an equal claim.
Thus, the fact that Brakhage's images are, in a sense, “mere”
juxtapositions, does not by any means force us into an abstract [i.e., purely
formal] viewing, purely in terms of light, shadow, color, rhythm, etc. On the contrary, it frees us to search for
the meanings that we ourselves can find as we struggle with our own
associations.[14]
I am now in a position to draw some
provisional conclusions. Clearly the
importance of Brakhage goes beyond the great praise that has been heaped upon
him as a unique, isolated “genius,” whose work is utterly subjective, thus
beyond rational analysis. While many
aspects of his films are highly personal; while he probably does put himself in
something like a trance state in order to free associate filmically; while he
often writes about his work in transcendental, even “cosmic” terms; we have
seen, nevertheless that this work is fundamentally grounded in structural
principles that can yield to analysis; that can be discussed objectively; that
do, in fact have precedents with which they can be compared. Far from being either a formal purist or
formless romantic, he has been able to transcend such alternatives in the
creation of films which are simultaneously documents, subjective visions, and
highly disciplined structures.
[1] “Camera
Lucida Camera Obscura,” in Artforum
XI, 5, Jan. 1973, pp. 31,32.
[2]
Visionary
Film (New York:Oxford University
Press, 1974) p. 233.
[3]
Abstract
Film and Beyond (Cambridge,
Mass. :MIT Press, 1977) pp. 88-90.
[4] “Stan and
Jane Brakhage Talking,'' interview with Hollis Frampton, in Artforum XI, Jan. 1973), pp.
76‑79.
[5] Metaphors on Vision (New York:Film Culture, 1963) unpaginated.
[6]
Ibid.,
(unpaginated).
[7]
Op.
cit., p. 37.
[8]
The foregoing should serve, among other
things, as a refutation of the “subjective viewpoint” theory, proposed by
Sitney and others, for which a typical Brakhage film “postulates the film‑maker
behind the camera as the first‑person protagonist of the film.” [see Sitney, Visionary Film, Op. Cit., p.
180].
[9] Brakhage,
op. cit.
[10]
Passages
in Modern Sculpture (New York:
Viking Press, 1977), p. 53.
[11]
Visionary
Film, op. cit.
p. 175.
[12]
Ibid.,
p. 216.
[13]
“Autobiography in Avant‑Garde Film” in The Avant‑Garde Film, ed. P. Adams Sitney (New York:New York University
Press, 1978), pp. 217, 219‑223.
[14]
Fred Camper, in an essay that came to my
attention only shortly before completing the final revision of my book, has
expressed views gratifyingly close to my own.
For example: “No Brakhage film can be simply seen, but rather the viewer
must continually struggle to see and resee it; and watching it becomes a
continually shifting exploration of the very process of seeing.” [“Stan Brakhage:A Retrospective,” notes by
Fred Camper, for the 1976 Los Angeles International Film Exposition]. Camper's essay reveals a rare grasp of the
role of disjunction and multireferentiality in Brakhage's work.
Similar insights, less rigorously
presented, can be found in Gene Youngblood's Expanded Cinema (New York: Dutton, 1970), especially in his
discussion of “synaesthetic cinema,” pp.
75‑91. While much in Youngblood’s
book seems, in retrospect, rather naively “Sixties-ish,” many of his comments
on Brakhage still, for me, have real validity.
No comments:
Post a Comment