The Myth of Post‑Modernism
I will say at the
outset that I am involved in what I call “neomodernism,” which may be defined
as a return to the most fundamental tenets of "formalist" modernism.
This may seem an odd occupation in an era when we are apparently escaping from
the long hegemony of modernism. Why return to modernism on the very threshold
of a new style period: post‑modernism?
My answer is that there is something very suspicious about this "postmodernism."
Everyone who uses the
term seems to have a different idea of what "post‑modernism" is
supposed to be. For some, it begins with John Cage, Jasper Johns, Rauschenberg,
"happenings" and concept art. For others it begins with the
minimalist reaction against that sort of thing. Many intellectuals associate
it with reflexive strategies growing out of structuralism. Anti‑intellectuals welcome
it as a relief from strategies of any kind, a return to less problematic
expressive modes which had been popular before modernism became dominant. Even
this group is divided among proponents of straight realism, narrative, fantasy,
decorative abstraction, punk and "new wave." Until we can agree on
when post‑modernism began, it is impossible to determine whether it is really
new. Until we can decide what it actually is, regarding it as a style period
would be premature.
If post‑modernism can
in fact only be defined negatively, as a rejection of modernism, of this rejection
we can be certain. Hardly a month passes when we are not made aware of yet
another brave sally against the modernist goliath in the form of a book,
magazine article or television series. Virtually everyone writing on the arts
seems to be breathlessly celebrating their liberation from the "pretensions"
of artists to whom they had once shamelessly deferred.
Seen in this light post‑modernism
is certainly real. But new? No artistic movement has been declared
"over" as many times as modernism. Expressionism, Neo‑Classicism,
Dada, Surrealism, Social Realism, Folclorismo,
the New Humanism, Pop Art, Earth Art, New Realism, Concept Art, Punk Art:
all were created as reactions against modernism. With the advent of each,
modernism was declared "over."
Now, of course, no one
would dream of declaring Pop Art "over;" we can look forward to no mea culpas from Artforum confessing that Surrealism is no longer "valid."
No one needs to declare that any of them are "over" for the simple
reason that all of them really are over.
The most interesting of these movements live on only in so far as they have
managed to become identified with modernism through some quirk of history.
It is true, of course,
that the current situation seems new in the extremity of the attack and the
apparent total victory of the opposition. We are, however, reliving an old and
rather trite script, straight out of the Thirties. Exactly the same things were
being said then as now. The same arguments, the same mea culpas, the mistrust of innovation, the need to look to the
past. And the art, in a strange way, was similar too.
A Modernist A B C
In my opinion we will
not get very far regarding modernism as a style period like the Renaissance,
Baroque or Rococo. It is much more fundamental, something that will be with us
for a very long time whether we like it or not.
In order to understand
this, it is necessary to be more precise with our use of the term. We need, in
fact, to think in terms of three "modernisms," which we can refer to
as "A," "B." and "C." "A" can also be
called "classic" or "formalist" modernism, which must be
defined narrowly in terms of a very specific body of work: the Cubism of
Picasso, Braque, Gris and Leger; Mondrian; much of Schönberg and Berg; almost
all of Webern; certain works of Stravinsky; James Joyce and possibly Gertrude
Stein. Some other, later figures, including Boulez, early Stockhausen and
Brakhage are also important.
To me, "A" modernism
is the true high road of Twentieth Century expression, a vigorous and profound
reaction against the prevailing romantic idealism of the previous century. It
represents something entirely new, something that will still be new and strange
to us many years from now. A fundamental change of such depth is bound to be
deeply threatening and, in fact, true modernism has been strongly resisted at
every stage of its development.
Both “B”
and "C" modernism can only be understood as forms of resistance to authentic
modernism, despite the fact that they are so often associated with it.
"B" modernism, often referred to as "hypermodernism,"
embraces some of the more obvious surface characteristics of "A,"
and, in fact, aggressively carries them to extremes. While it has usually
consciously allied itself with "A," it is my contention that the
masters of “B" modernism (and there have been some truly great ones) have
unconsciously sought to undermine true modernism. For "B" modernism
is really the continuation of late romanticism in modernist guise. The
flamboyantly extremist utopian rhetoric of such groups as the Futurists and
Constructivists is typical of “B"
modernism at its most aggressively ultra‑romantic.
A more subdued late
romanticism, leaning heavily toward subjective idealism, pervades the work and
thought of Kandinsky, expressionist movements like the Blau Reiter and much of abstract expressionism.
"C" modernism
is usually more consciously antimodernist, so much so that the fact that it is
considered a form of modernism at all is quite interesting and highly ironic.
Its purpose is to subvert what it regards as ''modernism'' by revealing its
contradictions, debunking its "pretentions" and emphasizing that to
which it is opposed. "C" modernism has taken many forms, some of the
most extreme being dada, surrealism, pop art, concept art, minimalism, systems
art, photo realism, etc. Despite the many obvious differences among these
trends, all are fundamentally "reflexive." A reflexive work
represents ("signifies") itself and, in so doing, promotes further
"reflection" on the manner of its coming into existence and the
process through which that existence is perceived and thought.
Reflexivity and Modernism
A great deal of
confusion has grown from the very mistaken idea that there is something modern
about reflexivity. This strategy is, on the contrary, both very old and
fundamentally reactionary, having cropped up again and again throughout history
as a means of ''demonstrating'' the futility of any new idea or practice. It is
intimately connected with the tradition of skepticism.
Of course, great
thinkers like Socrates have put skepticism to meaningful use in building
thought. What enraged him about the skepticism of the Sophists, however, was
their willingness to rest content with the contradictions they so cleverly
revealed. The smug self‑satisfaction of the Sophists has been inherited by
their Twentieth Century counterparts, the “C" modernists. The fundamental
message has remained the same down through the ages: "All thought is
pointless, all action futile, but aren't I clever?"
The various reflexive
strategies employed by "C" modernists can be complex, often requiring
detailed “deconstructive" analysis of a sort for which I have neither
inclination nor time. Fortunately, a relatively simple example exists, from the
career of the most sophisticated and interesting of the "C"
modernists: Marcel Duchamp.
In 1912, Duchamp was
humiliated by the rejection of his Nude
Descending a Staircase at the hands of the group of Cubists with whom he
had come to be associated. Within a few years he had left for the United States
and declared war on the modern movement.
The most notorious of
his many attempts to undermine modernism, as he understood it, was the well
known ''readymade'' entitled Fountain: an
ordinary urinal placed upside down, signed and exhibited as a work of art. This
"work," a perfect example of the fundamental equivalence of
reflexivity and parody, was intended to debunk what Duchamp perceived as the
essence of modernism: an elitist search for the "spiritual" as pure
form, signifying nothing, with no function other than disinterested
contemplation.
When seen completely
out of context a urinal can look very
much like a ''modernist'' sculpture with the purest of forms. Yet it does have a function, one which can
hardly be characterized as "spiritual." In the special context which
Duchamp very cleverly created for it, the urinal becomes a powerful signifier,
reflecting back upon itself as both ordinary object and ''modernist'' icon,
inviting the thoughtful viewer to equate the uselessness of abstract sculpture
with the uselessness of urine.
Despite its genuine
cleverness, this, like all of Duchamp's barbs at modernism, falls wide of the
mark. What Duchamp has assumed to be the essence of modernism is in fact
characteristic only of “B" modernism, with its typically late romantic
need for pure spirituality as "significant form." This has nothing to
do with "A" modernism which, in fact, begins by disrupting form. Nor
is there anything in "A" modernism that seeks to place itself above
the most ordinary objects and situations: think of Les Demoiselles d'Avignon, or a typical Cubist tabletop, or the use
of bits of newspaper and wall paper in early synthetic Cubism. In its early
stages, "A" modernism revels in the ordinary, the particular, even
the debased. Its purpose at this point is in fact very similar to that of
Duchamp.
Beyond
the Reflexive
Here we
are touching on an issue that is the source of the greatest confusions. Early
"A" modernism is indeed destructive in a manner very similar to the
destructiveness of "C" modernism and in fact is characterized by the
use of reflexive strategies. But there is a development beyond reflexiveness which carries the true modernists into
completely new territory. By the time we reach late Cubism, for example, the
self‑referential element is no longer dominant. With Mondrian it is completely
absent. "A" modernism uses reflexive strategies as a lever to open up
ambiguities which are then, eventually, resolved
on another level. More precisely, ambiguities in signification or
representation (referentiality) are resolved in the form of precise perceptual
determinations which no longer signify but can be powerfully expressive
nevertheless.
Although I am reluctant
to use a term which has become almost empty through over‑ and mis‑ use, there
is something very "dialectical" (in the Hegelian sense) about the
evolution of "A" modernism. Reflexivity is a circular process in
which something calls signification into question by signifying itself. But it simultaneously asserts signification since it operates by signifying (itself). To understand the real nature of this
"dialectic" (the basis for both "C" modernism and current
"deconstructionist" criticism) let us consider its central issue,
what we may call the "paradox paradox" of thought.
Paradoxes are
"openings" of thought which, according to the skeptics, mark the
limit of what can be thought. Ultimately, so say the skeptics, there is a
fundamental paradox central to thought which in some strange sense makes
thought impossible. But thought is possible, in fact it is thought which has
led us to the paradox. Thus the paradox at the center of thought is itself a
paradox.
Is this a logical
problem or a mystification? I strongly suspect that this "paradox,"
far from being the limit of thought, is actually only a disguised form of the
fundamental ambiguity which makes thought possible in the first place and
which, moreover, created the illusion that thought is without any limit
whatsoever. Thus thought is ''limited'' by that which makes it seem unlimited.
Acceptance of the "paradox paradox" as a limit of thought is, in
effect, complicity in the fiction that thought is limitless, all powerful.
(Thus Derridaean deconstructionism "reduces" thought to an empty play
of signification only to have it return "paradoxically.")
"C" modernism
revels in this mystification. "A" modernism puts a halt to it by
completing the dialectical process. Going beyond the reflexive reductio ad absurdum, the true
modernists struggled to resolve signification back into its purely material
elements in such a way that these elements would no longer signify anything,
even themselves, but serve to determine and thus liberate sensory experience,
the repressed "other" of signification.
Thus "A"
modernism, by opening thought (iconographic signification) from outside itself (i.e., from the realm of
the senses), reveals the bad faith of a "paradox" which exists only
to disguise the fact that anything at all can
exist outside of thought. It is the difference between a dream in which one
tells oneself that one is "only dreaming'' yet continues nevertheless to
dream ("C" modernism and deconstructionism) and a situation where one
is shaken awake by someone in the real world outside the dream.
From Irony to an "Order of Sensuousness"
There is simply no way
to briefly and succinctly illustrate the extraordinarily subtle and complex
process alluded to above without a very real risk of misunderstanding. One must
work through the whole process to understand it fully. The following, drawn
from my own attempts at systematic treatment of the issue (in a monograph now
being revised), must be regarded, therefore, strictly as a vague and incomplete
sketch:
We may gain some notion
of the workings of "A" modernism by considering the relation of
Cubist practice to the traditional treatment of pictorial space. Basic is the
following equation: organization of space = syntax. The perspective system and
related conventions regarding the treatment of "realist" space are
equivalent to pictorial syntax.
In attacking
conventional space the Cubists thus were also attacking the process of
pictorial (iconographic) signification. This is why certain Cubist spatial
devices (such as reverse perspective) have the effect of paradoxes. The
reflexive process generated by such paradoxes is the source of Cubist irony.
In some sense, Picasso
and Braque could thus be regarded in the same light as Duchamp. But there is a
profound difference between a purely conceptual attack on signification and one
involving the treatment of space.
As is well known, the
Cubist attack on perspective depends on the liberation of what artists call
"negative space." The emergence of this space does more than simply
"flatten" the picture a la conventional
modernist theory. Negative space disrupts representation itself by attacking
that "positive" space which serves as its syntax. Thus negative space
(or, more precisely, that means of organization which promotes it) is
equivalent to what may be called "negative syntax," the analytic
dismemberment of signification.
While
negative space as negative syntax has a good deal in common with that purely
intellectual "negativity" generated by reflexive thought
("deconstruction"), the former has something which the latter lacks:
the ability to precisely determine a perceptual field. Thus reverse perspective
(for example) in the hands of Picasso or Braque is not simply a device for the
negation of the perspective illusion; it is also a division of a given surface
area into clearly differentiated, thus clearly perceptible, proportions. These
proportions, precisely determined by
means of perceptual intuition (not geometry),
become the basis for synthetic Cubism and the mature work of Mondrian.
Significantly, that which serves to disrupt perspective (and, indeed, all forms
of conceptually determined seeing) serves to liberate and establish what is
probably best called, in the words of Herbert Marcuse, the "order of
sensuousness" (probably the best translation of the much abused term,
"aesthetic").
Unfortunately,
modernist "theory" has become so encrusted with dogmatic and half‑digested
formulations of a kind which, at best, can serve only as a parody of the
process I am trying to describe, that its real significance can be overlooked
or taken for granted. The “order of sensuousness" must be clearly
distinguished from the mere assertion of
the sensory (and material) which is so characteristic of "B"
modernism and has received so much attention in the critical literature. I am
really speaking of what might be termed a sensory analogue of logic. Here
again, prevalence of the phrase "perceptual logic" in various
contexts associated more or less loosely with gestalt psychology can easily
lead to a reversal of my meaning. Negative syntax is the defeat of gestalt perception, the liberation of exactly those
elements repressed by the gestalt. At the same time, it is also opposed to the
ambiguity that arises when gestalts are simply disrupted in the absence of a
negative structure (as in Abstract
Expressionism, for example).
If my analysis is correct,
the advent of true modernism must be compared, not to the inception of a style,
trend or period, but to the founding of a new and profoundly significant discipline on the order of geometry,
logic or mathematics. We may then see, in the rigorous reductionism of Mondrian
(and Webern!), the first steps in the search for a completely new kind of
axiom, an "antimatter" of signification.
The
Current Situation
We ought by now to have
a clearer view of what everyone is calling "postmodernism." Despite
the confusing array of styles to which I alluded earlier, it is not difficult
to see that we are now experiencing a full scale revival of "C"
modernism. Almost without exception the fashionable art of the day is an art in
quotation marks. Even that art which seems to be seeking authenticity is really
only seeking "authenticity." Any conceivable image or thing is
acceptably postmodern as long as it carries the sign of reflexivity, as long
as it is clear that the artist doesn't really mean it, that the thing is intended
as a sign for itself as something else.
It now becomes apparent
that the source of the current reaction against “modernism'' lies in the
fundamentally destructive, skeptical and reactionary nature of reflexivity
itself. It is also clear that this sort of "post‑modernism" can have
no future apart from that modernism which it seeks to debunk. Like the
strategies of post‑structuralist "deconstructionism," to which it is
closely allied, "C" modernism lacks (or refuses) that material,
sensory basis on which it could resolve its vicious circle. Ultimately it must
feed on and destroy itself. The only
way beyond the vicious circle is the
path already blazed by the modernist masters.
Of course, there is
another alternative. As I have already pointed out, the present period is much
like the Thirties, which was also preceded by an explosion of “C” modernism.
Most Thirties artists eventually recoiled from anything remotely reflexive or modernist to promote a
"sincerity" which was in fact the height of bad faith, a cultivated
naivete. This sort of thing is now being revived and, I fear, may be inspiring
those with the "smarts" to take a fling at sincerity (without
quotation marks).
This is a depressing
prospect, because in our time an educated person, certainly one with a
knowledge of history, cannot simply decide to be sincere. Sincerity is either
the result of a true naivete or the fruit of long years of research and self‑examination.
Neomodernism and The Cult of the New
Long years of research
and self‑examination. This ultimately is the meaning of neomodernism, engaged
as it is in the most difficult of tasks: the search for the fundamental
principles of “A” modernism. Such a search, combining creative work with the
most rigorous approach to theory, is not likely to appeal to budding post‑modernists.
It would, indeed, fly in the face of the prevalent myth that an enormous body
of theory devoted to modernism already exists, to the point that everyone is
now thoroughly “tired of' it. There are certainly signs of fatigue, but these
can hardly be due to overinvolvement with modernist theory, if by that we mean
a body of systematic thought devoted to central theoretical issues of modern
art. Such works are very few and far between.
A huge historical and
critical literature undoubtedly exists. And this literature reveals an enormous
obsession with issues of a theoretical nature. But if one reads closely, one
finds that each historian and critic usually presents us with his own
theoretical patchwork amplified by references to certain philosophers and
psychologists. The few works of a specifically art theoretical nature which do
exist are rarely cited in subsequent literature as the basis for a key concept.
Significantly, the many current attacks on modernist theory are usually
directed at Clement Greenberg, an influential theory‑minded critic but hardly
the author of a coherent. sustained theoretical work.
There is undoubtedly a
great deal of what passes for theory in the literature on modern art. Most of
this is and always has been tiresome. Of genuine theory there is still a
serious lack.
Modernism is of course
difficult. But the difficulty of the task before us is in fact its saving
grace. Neomodernism takes too much time and effort to be compatible with the
cult of the new, so often mistaken for modernism, which gives rise to an
endless series of mutually destructive trends. The so‑called
"pluralism" of the present time is simply an explosion of this cult
of the new into an uncontrollable frenzy of eccentricities. Behind this
"trend of no trends" is in fact very clearly the trend I have already
described: the revival of the reflexive strategies of “C” modernism. The next
trend will most likely be the bogus search for
sincerity-without-quotation-marks. There will be no lack of others, equally
superficial and redundant.
The serious artist has
always been the victim of such trends, which leave him or her maximally
vulnerable to the gallery owner, curator, critic and. most recently, arts
administrator. Despite all its difficulties, neomodernism can give the artist
powerful theoretical tools with which to resist.
No comments:
Post a Comment